Skip to content
ADVERTISEMENT
Sign In
  • Sections
    • News
    • Advice
    • The Review
  • Topics
    • Data
    • Diversity, Equity, & Inclusion
    • Finance & Operations
    • International
    • Leadership & Governance
    • Teaching & Learning
    • Scholarship & Research
    • Student Success
    • Technology
    • Transitions
    • The Workplace
  • Magazine
    • Current Issue
    • Special Issues
    • Podcast: College Matters from The Chronicle
  • Newsletters
  • Virtual Events
  • Ask Chron
  • Store
    • Featured Products
    • Reports
    • Data
    • Collections
    • Back Issues
  • Jobs
    • Find a Job
    • Post a Job
    • Professional Development
    • Career Resources
    • Virtual Career Fair
  • More
  • Sections
    • News
    • Advice
    • The Review
  • Topics
    • Data
    • Diversity, Equity, & Inclusion
    • Finance & Operations
    • International
    • Leadership & Governance
    • Teaching & Learning
    • Scholarship & Research
    • Student Success
    • Technology
    • Transitions
    • The Workplace
  • Magazine
    • Current Issue
    • Special Issues
    • Podcast: College Matters from The Chronicle
  • Newsletters
  • Virtual Events
  • Ask Chron
  • Store
    • Featured Products
    • Reports
    • Data
    • Collections
    • Back Issues
  • Jobs
    • Find a Job
    • Post a Job
    • Professional Development
    • Career Resources
    • Virtual Career Fair
    Upcoming Events:
    An AI-Driven Work Force
    University Transformation
Sign In
Left to right: Iris Murdoch, Philippa Foot, Elizabeth Anscombe, and Mary Midgley

Metaphysical Animals

The four women who transformed 20th-century analytic philosophy.

The Review | Essay
By Clare Mac Cumhaill and Rachael Wiseman April 8, 2022

“Work should not be discontinued on the sounding of sirens.” So read a notice on the first page of The Oxford Magazine on November 21, 1940, just over a year into World War II. Sirens, in that difficult year, sounded all too frequently — so the notice instructed students to rely also on the word of volunteers charged with identifying enemy planes from the roofs of the University of Oxford’s colleges. Those rooftop “spotters” were trained “to give warning of the near approach of danger during daylight.” Mary Scrutton, a philosophy student at Somerville College, was not a spotter. Instead, while not studying, she spent freezing afternoons planting potatoes in hard clayey soil, or packing books for the Red Cross to send to prisoners of war. At lunchtime, she made her way to the college dining room to eat whatever the beleaguered cooks could invent. It is over one such lunch that a little-known story in the history of philosophy begins.

To continue reading for FREE, please sign in.

Sign In

Or subscribe now to read with unlimited access for as low as $10/month.

Don’t have an account? Sign up now.

A free account provides you access to a limited number of free articles each month, plus newsletters, job postings, salary data, and exclusive store discounts.

Sign Up

“Work should not be discontinued on the sounding of sirens.” So read a notice on the first page of The Oxford Magazine on November 21, 1940, just over a year into World War II. Sirens, in that difficult year, sounded all too frequently — so the notice instructed students to rely also on the word of volunteers charged with identifying enemy planes from the roofs of the University of Oxford’s colleges. Those rooftop “spotters” were trained “to give warning of the near approach of danger during daylight.” Mary Scrutton, a philosophy student at Somerville College, was not a spotter. Instead, while not studying, she spent freezing afternoons planting potatoes in hard clayey soil, or packing books for the Red Cross to send to prisoners of war. At lunchtime, she made her way to the college dining room to eat whatever the beleaguered cooks could invent. It is over one such lunch that a little-known story in the history of philosophy begins.

Iris Murdoch, Mary Midgley, Philippa Foot, and Elizabeth Anscombe are now recognized as among the most important philosophers of the last century. But their philosophical lives began as undergraduates in an Oxford disrupted by World War II. They met first over ration-book lunches in Somerville, one of Oxford’s four colleges for women. Mary Scrutton (later Midgley) was tall and gangly. She was more interested in newts and animal life than in trying to appear dainty, which was just as well when “digging for victory” on a windy Headington Hill. Iris Murdoch was a dashing Irish-born communist — exuberant and vivacious. If Something Was Happening, Iris was sure to be there, notebook in hand. Philippa Bosanquet (later Foot), pathologically discreet and ferociously bright, had rebelled against her mother’s best-laid plans to have her well-married. Esther Bosanquet (a daughter of President Grover Cleveland) despaired as her elder daughter set herself on getting An Education: “Don’t worry dear, she doesn’t look clever,” one of Esther’s friends consoled. Elizabeth Anscombe was a brilliant Catholic convert, inclined to wear trousers and already notorious for self-publishing a pamphlet claiming to give the Catholic view on “The Justice of the Present War.” (She and her co-author were forced to withdraw it on the orders of the bishop of Birmingham.) The four women shared books when paper shortages made copies scarce. While sirens wailed, they sat through lectures delivered by unconscripted women, conscientious objectors, old men, and the refugee scholars who had fled Nazi anti-Semitic legislation for the pavements of Oxford.

Hardly anyone in philosophy seemed to be aware that these women had worked and written and philosophized together. Why?

In the five decades that followed, these four friends would produce some of the best-known works of contemporary philosophy, especially in the field of ethics. Anscombe’s “Modern Moral Philosophy” and Foot’s “Moral Beliefs” and “Moral Arguments” are the foundational texts of contemporary virtue ethics. Anscombe’s Intention has been described as the most important work in the philosophy of action since Aristotle. Foot’s Natural Goodness is a modern classic. Murdoch’s The Sovereignty of Good introduced the notions of “moral psychology” and “moral vision” into the philosophical lexicon, and her Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals is beginning to gain the scholarly attention it deserves — for some, it is a masterpiece. Mary Midgley might be claimed to be the founding mother of contemporary animal ethics. Her Beast and Man is the first work in philosophical ethology, and remains a touchstone for today’s ecofeminists.

Until recently, however, no one had remarked that these four women were contemporaries, let alone friends. No one had noticed the significance of what Mary Midgley had insisted in her memoir The Owl of Minerva: that she and her university friends received the attention that their talents deserved only because of the war. There were, she said, fewer men around to shout them down. And no one had seriously thought to read these women’s work together, nor to read closely the work of those who taught them while they were not scanning the skies or digging potatoes. As it turns out, what historians of philosophy had failed to spot was a pattern of thinking that animates the philosophy of all four women. Might these four friends constitute an all-female philosophical school?

All four certainly share a vision of what philosophy is for. Philosophy is necessary when (as Anscombe puts it) we are “in the dark about the character of our concepts.” Mary Midgley and Philippa Foot both compare philosophy to plumbing. “If you have trouble with your pipes you call in a plumber, if you have trouble with your concepts you call in a philosopher,” explained Foot. Iris Murdoch writes of the “darkness of practical reason” and of the mystery each of us is unto one another, of the pull of fantasy and the difficulty of real attention. Where analytic philosophers typically insist on extreme abstract clarity and precision — on arguments that can be formalized into a tidy set of premises and an unambiguous conclusion — these women take as their starting point darkness, confusion, and disorientation. They recognize that even the most rigorous and careful statements may be misunderstood, misinterpreted, and misapplied. Any neat formulation is bound to leave something out. In different ways, they all argue that metaphors and analogies are indispensable to philosophical thinking and that philosophers must rely on others to catch hold of what they say.

It is no accident that they met as undergraduates during World War II and developed their philosophy in the wake of the Holocaust and Hiroshima.

In the years immediately following the war, when Oxford teemed with men returned from fighting and the intelligence services, the four women had research studentships or part-time tutoring roles at Oxford and Cambridge. They met regularly in Philippa’s front room at 16 Park Town, Oxford. While Plato and politics had been among the topics of their conversations in the Somerville dining hall, they now asked, What are we going to do about this? — the this accompanied with a gesture toward the philosophy that was gripping the men’s colleges, and that seemed to them utterly inadequate to the enormity and horror of what had just happened.

Oxford philosophy in the postwar period owed its character to the new analytic and logical methods that had embedded themselves in Oxford and Cambridge in the interwar period, popularized in A.J. Ayer’s 1936 manifesto, Language, Truth and Logic. Ayer proposed that everyday language could be formalized and clarified with the new logical symbolism developed by Bertrand Russell and Gottlob Frege. Once formalized, observational judgments could be tested, one by one, by appeal to sensory experience. Any proposition that did not yield to this analysis and method of testing failed to express a thought, Ayer claimed. For example, “There are mountains on the far side of the moon” is, in principle, verifiable. We know what it would take for the statement to be true — we would need to travel to the far side of the moon and observe mountains of some estimable height there. But there is no procedure we could use, no observations we could make, to prove or disprove metaphysicians’ claims about the nature of a transcendent reality, God, Truth, or Beauty. Ethical discourse also failed Ayer’s test — after all, there is no quality that we could observe to determine the truth or falsity of “stealing is bad.” So, such discourse was classified as merely expressive — a moral argument came down to the exchange of shouts of “Boo!” and “Hooray!”

Clockwise from top: Elizabeth Anscombe, Mary Midgley, Philippa Foot, and Iris Murdoch
Clockwise from top: Elizabeth Anscombe, Mary Midgley, Philippa Foot, and Iris MurdochIllustration by Valerie Chiang; photos from Getty Images, Guardian/eyevine

In Ayer’s vision, the ancient conception of philosophy as the painstaking and lifelong task of contemplating our purpose and place in the world, and of seeking to live in accord with those discoveries, was replaced by a modern technique. The philosopher’s task was to regiment statements into a symbolic language, the constituents of which corresponded to possible experiences, before handing them over to scientists to be tested by observation. With this method in hand, a whole generation of young philosophers was excited to discover that they could brush aside any hesitating talk of the metaphysical by roundly and loudly declaring, “I don’t understand.” “What comes next?,” a friend asked Ayer soon after the publication of Language, Truth and Logic. “There’s no next,” replied Ayer. “Philosophy has come to an end. Finished.”

Ayer was wrong about that, but his book had a profound impact. Much of the philosophy produced in Britain in the 1940s and 1950s remained shaped by his vision of the task of philosophy as linguistic clarification and the exposing of nonsense. J.L. Austin, an Oxford professor a few years younger than Ayer, had been in the intelligence services during the war and was newly attuned to the code-breaking possibilities that analysis of linguistic data afforded. He continued Ayer’s mission to eradicate nonsense in his famous “Saturday morning” gatherings. These took place in the men’s colleges, and all Oxford’s young philosophers were invited — except the women. In Austin’s hands, the weaponized “I don’t understand” took on a new form. For him, the “ordinary man” in the street was the arbiter of sense, and the measure by which complex metaphysical concepts like Truth and Reality could be briskly dispatched. Richard Hare, who attended the Saturday-morning classes, took moral philosophy further along the path that began from Ayer’s basic picture of a world stripped of value. In his hands “Hooray!” and “Boo!” became the more sophisticated “Do it!” and “Don’t.”

The male philosophers’ refusal to say anything that could not be said clearly or using “ordinary language” — their conviction that the purposes of philosophy must be subsumed by science, and their denial that reality constrains what is good or bad, right or wrong — repelled all four of the friends. As they sat in Philippa Foot’s front room, they responded unanimously. Mary Midgley retained “a persisting memory” of those gatherings:

[We were] doing our collective best to answer the orthodoxies of the day, which we all saw as disastrous. As with many philosophical schools, the starting-point was a joint “NO!” No (that is) at once to divorcing Facts from Values, and — after a bit more preparation — also No to splitting mind off from matter. From this, a lot of metaphysical consequences would follow.

The metaphysics that followed over the coming decades is copious and profound. The women saw that the problem with the philosophy that dominated that postwar setting wasn’t restricted to moral philosophy as such. The speechlessness of the moral philosophers in the face of the Holocaust was rather a symptom of a deeper malaise. Lying behind the “Boo!” “Hooray!” ethics was a picture of human individuals as “efficient calculating machines,” concerned only with the manipulation of symbols and the recording of experiential data. This framing alienated a person not just from her own animal nature, but also from her history, her culture, her practical rationality, and the friends, lovers, and children that made up her life.

By stamping out nonsense, the men had shut philosophers out from the very area in which they should work: the dark. For the four women, human life is a mix of instinct and culture. We are constantly running up against the limits of our own perspective and the puzzles that life throws up. It is in our nature, as “metaphysical animals,” to ask questions that go beyond the limits of what we experience here and now, and to create pictures, images, and stories that shape our ways of going on. There is a form of the question “Why?,” the friends insisted, that comes naturally to children and that we, as adults, must continue to use. Why should I share my pencils? Why are the lives of animals important? Why do people lie? This “Why?” cannot be met by the sorts of explanation that belong to science. Instead, the question invites us to turn our attention to what is mysterious and paradoxical in this deeply puzzling, teeming world.

ADVERTISEMENT

When we met Mary Midgley in 2015, the 95-year-old “metaphysical animal” told us this remarkable story. Had it not been for the interruption of the war, she said, she and her friends would probably not have found themselves in Foot’s living room, devising their highly unfashionable response to the philosophical scene in which they found themselves. “Another war is not to be recommended,” she explained with characteristic humor. “But yes, it was because of the war that we got through.” Once war had been declared, the young men and the “Big Beasts” of the new analytic philosophy (A.J. Ayer, J.L. Austin, and R.M. Hare, among them) were uprooted from Oxford and replanted in Whitehall and the War Office. As young men volunteered or were conscripted, women were no longer an extreme minority in lecture rooms and seminars.

That shift, Midgley later reflected, changed the climate in the classroom.

The trouble is not, of course, men as such — men have done good enough philosophy in the past — what is wrong is a particular style of philosophizing that results from encouraging a lot of clever young men to compete in winning arguments ... By contrast, in those wartime classes — which were small — men (conscientious objectors etc.) were present as well as women but they weren’t keen on arguing. It is clear that we all were more interested in understanding this deeply puzzling world than in putting each other down.

And it was not just the climate that changed: The content of their philosophical education changed too. With the younger analytic philosophers away, the older metaphysicians were asked to return to the lecterns to cover the teaching. They spoke once again of transcendence, wisdom, and truth. Refugee academics, fleeing Nazi persecution in Austria and Germany, stepped in to take classes. Speaking in a language that was not their own, they shared scholarship and learning of a kind Oxford had not seen before. Philosophers and classicists including Raymond Klibansky, Ernst and Heinz Cassirer, Richard Walzer, and Lotte Labowsky all appeared on the lecture lists. And moral philosophy’s ancient problems about the relationships between duty and goodness and between happiness and virtue took on concrete form in the minds of the conscientious objectors who had refused conscription.

ADVERTISEMENT

All four women were taught by Donald MacKinnon, a pacifist and Scottish Episcopalian. A young man of towering physique, MacKinnon attracted animal epithets: bear-headed, lion-pawed, owl-eyed. He spoke with a Scottish growl. Working with him was “a remarkable stroke of luck,” said Midgley. “He created me,” Foot later said of MacKinnon. For Murdoch he was “a jewel.” MacKinnon was a few years younger than A.J. Ayer, and he, perhaps more than anyone else in Oxford at that time, saw the significance and potency of Ayer’s attempt to kill off metaphysics. “The elimination of metaphysics is before all else an assault on man in the interests of a method,” he wrote. “It prepares man for his ‘subordination’ to the process of empirical science.”

It was during those early conversations that Foot first realized the importance of virtue, Anscombe developed her interest in human life and action, Murdoch became concerned with mystery and vision, and Midgley first began to ask deeply unfashionable questions about the animality of human life.

One aspect of that subordination, as MacKinnon saw it, was the loss of that distinctive sense of the question “Why?” that characterizes the curiosity of the philosopher. Aristotle’s rational animal employs many forms of explanation and inquiry to make sense of its world — the question “Why?” might ask for an explanation in terms of efficient causation, but it might also ask for an account of a larger pattern of human activity, or to appeal to a telos (purpose) or fit. In contrast, the logical positivist’s assimilation of human reason to the activities of calculation and symbolic manipulation cut rationality loose from comprehension. If the “stuff of the physical world” is merely the data of sensory experience, the request for explanation — Why? — would be limited to a prediction based on past observations, and the human capacity for reason would be understood solely in terms of a capacity for “the elaboration of technical devices whereby the order of our sensations may be predicted and controlled.”

Humans are metaphysical animals, MacKinnon told his tutees. We are not “efficient calculating machines” but living creatures whose characteristic form of life shapes what we need to live well. As well as food and shelter, we need society and love. But we are limited in what we can know and understand. The “Why?” that is the mark of the metaphysical animal emerges of necessity in this context, the context of human life in which we are confronted with a reality that defies our capacity to understand it. The snowdrop hangs its head. Why? So asked a 6-year-old Iris Murdoch in 1925. “Why indeed!” she reflected as an adult. “A thought-provoking question, a good introduction to a world which is full of mysteries.”

ADVERTISEMENT

In a diary entry from 1948, Murdoch describes one of these sessions as philosophy in a “world of women”: “I reflected, talking with Mary, Pip and Elizabeth, how much I love them.” The fact that there was such a “world of women” did catch the attention of some of the men returning to Oxford in the late 1940s, and the women’s “invasion of the field” in their absence was a subject of some concern. When, in 1956, Elizabeth Anscombe protested Oxford’s decision to award former President Harry Truman an honorary degree — she argued that his decision to use the atomic bomb was mass murder — a rumor spread around the men’s colleges: “The women are up to something.” Though Oxford awarded the honorary degree anyway, Anscombe’s protest brought new attention to the university’s female philosophers. The following year, Richard Hare described the group in a tone of injured pride:

We are lucky enough to have in Oxford, in the women’s colleges, a number of able and distinguished philosophers; and most of them spend quite a lot of the time attacking the views of their male colleagues. They all, when I am the target, accuse me of paying too much attention to general principles and too little to the peculiarity of individual cases — which require to be savoured with a feminine intuition before a right moral judgment can be passed upon them.

Despite the sense that something was going on in the women’s colleges, the quartet did not gain a reputation as a school. When we discovered their story, in 2015, hardly anyone in philosophy seemed to be aware that these women had known one another, let alone that they had worked and written and philosophized together. Why?

Philosophical schools are usually named by their opponents. When a set of voices is recognized as posing a challenge to an orthodoxy, or seen as articulating an alternative that can no longer be ignored, they are grouped, named, and challenged. But when the voices are “over in the women’s colleges,” their proclaimed status as “able and distinguished philosophers” can be quite easily undercut by characterizing their interventions as mere appeals to “feminine intuition.” Philippa, Elizabeth, Iris, and Mary did each manage to “get through” — as Mary would later put it — in a system both actively and unconsciously inhospitable to women. But what did not “get through” was the story of their friendship, of four brilliant women working together to figure out how philosophy might go on. It was during those early conversations that Foot first realized the importance of virtue, Anscombe developed her interest in human life and action, Murdoch became concerned with mystery and vision, and Midgley first began to ask deeply unfashionable questions about the animality of human life. Without the other three, each would have become a different kind of thinker.

It is only recently that philosophy has been ready to take seriously the possibility that this quartet might be worthy of naming as a school. There are at least two reasons to encourage this. First, philosophy and philosophers find many ways to dismiss, denigrate, ignore, and misattribute the work of women thinkers. Susan Stebbing, the brilliant logician who founded the journal Analysis, was a household name before her death, in 1943, but she was written out of the discipline’s canon almost immediately. There is safety and weight in numbers. Second, when read together, the work of these four brilliant individuals — each with her own philosophical temperament and style — interlocks to form a picture of our world, and our place in it, that is much deeper, more intellectually robust, and more metaphysically sophisticated than that of their male peers. Murdoch’s writings on love and attention, Foot’s on virtue and reason, Anscombe’s on action, and Midgley’s on human nature come together to describe a metaphysical animal, an animal whose life is shaped by love, parenting, plants, perfection, poetry, instinct, and promising. These women’s work and lives remind us where philosophy begins: with puzzlement, wonder, and the courage to ask “Why?”

We welcome your thoughts and questions about this article. Please email the editors or submit a letter for publication.
Tags
Scholarship & Research Gender Opinion
Share
  • Twitter
  • LinkedIn
  • Facebook
  • Email
About the Author
Clare Mac Cumhaill
Clare Mac Cumhaill is an associate professor of philosophy at Durham University and a co-director of the Women in Parenthesis project. She is the author, with Rachael Wiseman, of Metaphysical Animals: How Four Women Brought Philosophy Back to Life (Doubleday, 2022).
About the Author
Rachael Wiseman
Rachael Wiseman is a senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Liverpool and a co-director of the Women in Parenthesis project. She is the author of the Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Anscombe’s “Intention” (Routledge, 2016) and, with Clare Mac Cumhaill, of Metaphysical Animals: How Four Women Brought Philosophy Back to Life (Doubleday, 2022).
ADVERTISEMENT
ADVERTISEMENT

More News

Black and white photo of the Morrill Hall building on the University of Minnesota campus with red covering one side.
Finance & operations
U. of Minnesota Tries to Soften the Blow of Tuition Hikes, Budget Cuts With Faculty Benefits
Photo illustration showing a figurine of a football player with a large price tag on it.
Athletics
Loans, Fees, and TV Money: Where Colleges Are Finding the Funds to Pay Athletes
Photo illustration of a donation jar turned on it's side, with coins spilling out.
Access & Affordability
Congressional Republicans Want to End Grad PLUS Loans. How Might It Affect Your Campus?
Florida Commissioner of Education Manny Diaz, Jr. delivers remarks during the State Board of Education meeting at Winter Park High School, Wednesday, March 27, 2024.
Executive Privilege
In Florida, University Presidents’ Pay Goes Up. Is Politics to Blame?

From The Review

Photo illustration of a classical column built of paper, with colored wires overtaking it like vines of ivy
The Review | Essay
The Rise of a New Ed Tech Buzzword
By Kit Nicholls
William F. Buckley, Jr.
The Review | Interview
William F. Buckley Jr. and the Origins of the Battle Against ‘Woke’
By Evan Goldstein
Robert F. Kennedy, Jr.
The Review | Opinion
What RFK Jr. Got Right About Academic Publishing
By Robert M. Kaplan

Upcoming Events

Plain_Acuity_DurableSkills_VF.png
Why Employers Value ‘Durable’ Skills
Warwick_Leadership_Javi.png
University Transformation: A Global Leadership Perspective
Lead With Insight
  • Explore Content
    • Latest News
    • Newsletters
    • Letters
    • Free Reports and Guides
    • Professional Development
    • Virtual Events
    • Chronicle Store
    • Chronicle Intelligence
    • Jobs in Higher Education
    • Post a Job
  • Know The Chronicle
    • About Us
    • Vision, Mission, Values
    • DEI at The Chronicle
    • Write for Us
    • Work at The Chronicle
    • Our Reporting Process
    • Advertise With Us
    • Brand Studio
    • Accessibility Statement
  • Account and Access
    • Manage Your Account
    • Manage Newsletters
    • Individual Subscriptions
    • Group and Institutional Access
    • Subscription & Account FAQ
  • Get Support
    • Contact Us
    • Reprints & Permissions
    • User Agreement
    • Terms and Conditions
    • Privacy Policy
    • California Privacy Policy
    • Do Not Sell My Personal Information
1255 23rd Street, N.W. Washington, D.C. 20037
© 2025 The Chronicle of Higher Education
The Chronicle of Higher Education is academe’s most trusted resource for independent journalism, career development, and forward-looking intelligence. Our readers lead, teach, learn, and innovate with insights from The Chronicle.
Follow Us
  • twitter
  • instagram
  • youtube
  • facebook
  • linkedin